[1] Ingram Bywater & I. Bywater (eds.)Aristotle Ethica Nicomachea,Clarendon Press(1963). [2] Cooper,J. M.,(1975),Reason and Human Good in Aristotle(Cambridge,Mass.);(1987),Contemplation and happiness:a reconsideration,Synthese 72:187-216. [3] Lawrence,G.1993. Aristotle and the Ideal Life. Philosophical Review 102:1-34. [4] Kraut,R.,(1989),Aristotle on the Human Good,(Princeton). [5] Tuozzo,1995.Contemplation,the Noble,and the Mean:The Standard of Moral Virtue in Aristotle's Ethics Apeiron 28(4):129-154. [6] Rorty1980,The Place of Contemplation in Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics,in Rorty(ed.),Articles of Aristotle’s Ethics:pp.377-94. [7] Lear 2004,Happy Lives and the Highest Good. Princeton University Press.. [8] Jon Miller(ed.)2013,The Reception of Aristotle's Ethics. Cambridge University Press,2013. [9] Lesley Brown& Ross,D.(eds.)(2009). The Nicomachean Ethics. Oxford:OUP,242. [10] Dirlmeier,F.(1963).Aristoteles. Nikomachische Ethik,?beretzung und Erl?uterungen,in:Aristoteles,Werke in deutscher ?bersetzung,Bd. 6,Berlin.468. [11] Gauthier,R.A.,&Jolif,J.Y.(1958). Aristote:L Ethique a Nicomaque,2Bde. Louvain. Tome II-2,542-47. [12] Nagel(1972). Aristotle on Eudaimonia. Phronesis 17(3):252-259. [13] Moline,J.(1983),Contemplation and the Human Good,No?s,Vol.17,No. 1,37-53. [14] Heinaman,R.(1988),Eudaimoniaand self-sufficiency in the Nicomachean Ethics,Phronesis33:31-53. [15] Curzer,H.(1990),Criteria for Happiness in Nicomachean Ethics I7 and X6-8,Classical Quarterly,Vol.40,421-32. [16] D. Sedley(1999). The Ideal of Godlikeness. In G. Fine(ed.),Plato 2:Ethics,Politics,Religion,and the Soul. Oxford University Press. pp.309-28. [17] Klaus Corcilius (2008). Praktische Syllogismen bei Aristoteles. Archiv für Geschichte der Philosophie 90 (3):247-297. [18] W. F. R Hardie. (1980). Aristotle's Ethical Theory,2nd.ed. (Oxford);S. Clark. 1975. Aristotle's Man:Speculations Upon Aristotelian Anthropology,Oxford:Clarendon Press. |